2016 March 3rd
Presentation for the University of South Alabama
For the metric arc I=[0,1] and continuum-valued bonding relation f closed in I^2, the inverse limit lim{I,f,ω} is the subspace of the countable power I^ω containing sequences x satisfying x(n)∈f(x(n+1)). A recent trend in continuum theory is to generalize this notion to lim{I,f,L}, where L is an arbitrary linear order. When L=ω, the inverse limit is a subspace of the metrizable space I^ω; however, we will show that when L is uncountable, the inverse limit cannot be metrizable unless f is trivial. Furthermore, when L is an uncountable well order, it will be shown that the inverse limit is not even Corson compact.
\(\varprojlim\{I,f,L\}\subseteq I^L\) is metrizable.
\(\varprojlim\{I,\iota,L\}\cong I\) is metrizable
We now assume \(f\not=\iota\).
\(\varprojlim\{I,\gamma,\omega_1\}\) is the closed long ray of length \(\omega_1\), so not metrizable (or even Corson compact, \(W\), Frechet-Urysohn, etc.)
There exist \(x,y\in I\) such that \(\langle x,x\rangle,\langle x,y\rangle,\langle y,y\rangle\) are all in \(f\).
\(\Gamma\) trivially holds
Contradicts connectedness of \(f\).
Contradicts surjectivity and idempotence of \(f\).
Contradicts surjectivity and idempotence of \(f\).
Contradicts idempotence of \(f\).
Now that \(\Gamma\) has been verified for our bonding relations, we may restrict our attention to the two-point discrete space \(2=\{0,1\}\) and investigate \(\varprojlim\{2,\gamma,L\}\subseteq\varprojlim\{X,f,L\}\).
For any total order \(L\), we may define \(\check L=\{A\subseteq L:a\in L,b\lt a\Rightarrow b\in L\}\) which is totally ordered by \(\subseteq\).
Give \(\check L\) its usual order topology generated by the sets \((A,B)=\{C\in\check L:A\subsetneq C\subsetneq B\}\).
Note \(\check L\) is always a compact space.
Note that for \(\vec x\in\varprojlim\{2,\gamma,L\}\), a value of \(0\) may stay \(0\) or change to \(1\) as we look to the left.
But, once the value changes to \(1\), it's forced to stay there.
It follows that each \(\vec x\) is exactly the characteristic function \(\phi_A\) for some \(A\in \check L\); that is, \[ \vec x(l)=\phi_A(l)=\begin{cases} 1 & \text{if } l\in A \\ 0 & \text{if } l\not\in A \end{cases} \]
Note further that in the topology on \(\varprojlim\{2,\gamma,L\}\subseteq 2^L\), a basic open set may fix \(\vec x(a)=1\) and \(\vec x(b)=0\) for some \(a\lt b \in L\).
This is exactly the basic open set \(((\leftarrow,a),(\leftarrow,b])\) in \(\check L\).
Thus the map \(A\mapsto\phi_A\) is a homeomorphism from \(\check L\) to \(\varprojlim\{2,\gamma,L\}\).
Since we've found a copy of the compact space \(\check L\), we can break metrizability and other properties by showing that they cannot hold in \(\check L\).
Consider the totally ordered ordinal spaces such as \(0=\emptyset\), \(3=\{0,1,2\}\), \(\omega=\{0,1,2,\dots\}\), \(\omega+2=\{0,1,\dots,\omega,\omega+1\}\) ordered by \(\subseteq\).
Since \(\alpha+1=\alpha\cup\{\alpha\}\), it's not hard to see that \(\check\alpha=\alpha+1\) for every ordinal, including the first uncountable ordinal \(\omega_1\).
It's easy to show that every countable \(\alpha+1\) is metrizable.
But in fact, even the first uncountable successor \(\omega_1+1\) is not metrizable, or even a \(W\)-space.
Player \(\mathcal O\) wins if after \(\omega\) arounds, \(\lim_{n\to\infty}x_n=x\), and \(\mathcal P\) wins otherwise. \(x\) is a \(W\)-point if \(\mathcal O\) has an unbeatable strategy at that point.
In a metrizable space, it's obvious that every point is \(W\) since \(\mathcal O\) can simply choose radii converging to \(0\). Since every point is \(W\), it's a \(W\) space.
Because the game only lasts countably many rounds, \(\mathcal P\)'s' countable sequence must have an upper bound \(\beta\) in \(\omega_1\). Therefore \((\beta,\rightarrow)\) is a neighborhood of \(\omega_1\) missing every point in \(\mathcal P\)'s sequence.
We've shown that \(\check\alpha\) is metrizable (or even Corson compact, \(W\), Fréchet–Urysohn, etc. etc.) if and only if \(\alpha\) is countable.
More generally, it can be shown that \(\check L\) is metrizable if and only if \(L\) is countable, since \(\check L\)'s weight always equals its cardinality.
Thus a generalized inverse limit may only be metrizable when \(L\) is countable or \(f\) is trivial.
Slides available at Clontz.org.